Search results

Filters

  • Journals
  • Keywords
  • Date

Search results

Number of results: 25
items per page: 25 50 75
Sort by:
Download PDF Download RIS Download Bibtex

Abstract

The early philosophical standpoint of Professor Bogusław Wolniewicz alluded mainly to the so-called first philosophy of Ludwig Wittgenstein, as expressed in his Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus. Professor Wolniewicz’s views have found their expressions, first, in the book (in Polish) Things and Facts. An introduction to the first philosophy of Ludwig Wittgenstein (1968), and finally in his monograph (in Polish) Ontology of Situations. Foundations and Applications (1985). In both cases, Wolniewicz’ standpoint has been expressed by giving a substantive interpretation to semiotical and logical concepts (i.e. by producing hypostases). This practice looks rather dubious to me, in both cases, although I hope that ontology of situations can be usefully treated as a general formal theory of semantical correlates characteristic for sentential statements.

Go to article

Authors and Affiliations

Józef Andrzej Stuchliński
Download PDF Download RIS Download Bibtex

Abstract

Social ontology is a philosophical discipline on the basis of which an inquiry about the actual ontological status of such objects as money or churches can be undertaken. Such objects belong to socio-cultural reality. Within the field of social ontology philosophers look for answers to the following two questions: (Q1) How does an objective social reality arise? (Q2) How does an objective social reality continue to persist? Roman Ingarden conducted advanced research on the question of existence and on different forms of existence. He was also engulfed in the study of arts and culture. In this article I undertake to analyze Ingarden’s views on socio‑cultural reality and consider his position on the nature of social ontology. I also propose answers to questions (Q1) and (Q2).
Go to article

Authors and Affiliations

Artur Kosecki
1
ORCID: ORCID

  1. Uniwersytet Szczeciński, Instytut Filozofii i Kognitywistyki, ul. Krakowska 71/79, 71-017 Szczecin
Download PDF Download RIS Download Bibtex

Abstract

In the opinion of Bogusław Wolniewicz (1927–2017), Wittgenstein in his Tractatus presented a new metaphysics – a modern ‘metaphysics of facts’, in opposition to the traditional ‘metaphysics of substance’ (Aristotle) or to the ‘metaphysics of things’ (Tadeusz Kotarbiński’s ‘reism’). The new metaphysics describes, just like the old ones did, the structure of the world. First, it refers to the world as a whole, seeing in it an actualization of one of numerous possible worlds. It also refers to the elementary unit of world-structure, which is an ‘atomic fact’ (an independent unit, though at the same time not the simplest one, since it involves further ‘simple objects’). Those concepts of ‘world’, ‘atom’ and ‘possible beings’ make the system of Tractatus ‘metaphysics’, comparable to the Aristotle’s metaphysics of ‘form’ and ‘matter’. In Tractatus, the Aristotelian ‘matter’ turns into ‘simple objects’, while ‘form’ becomes a form of ‘fact’. In this view, the world is conceived as a set of facts and equals a particular choice made from the universe of possible situations. But one element is missing in Wittgenstein’s system, namely, the ‘efficient cause’ responsible for the choice of facts (actualization of possibilities). Leibniz believed there was a ‘sufficient reason’ why a particular choice was made among possible situations and one possible world has become real. This ‘sufficient reason’ finally turned out to be God’s rational will. In Wolniewicz’s late philosophy however, the ‘efficient cause’ is only ‘fate’ or ‘chance’ (τύχη). Fate is therefore the mysterious deus absconditus of Wittgenstein’s metaphysics.

Go to article

Authors and Affiliations

Łukasz Kowalik
ORCID: ORCID
Download PDF Download RIS Download Bibtex

Abstract

In this article I try to think about the terms “stories” and “ontologies” in Ewa Domańska’s works: Mikrohistorie. Spotkania w międzyświatach (1999; 2005), Historie niekonwencjonalne (2006), Historia egzystencjonalna (2012), Historia ratownicza (2014) and I try to compare my conclusions with her latest publication. I am interested in the turning point in her thoughts, giving up the theory and methodology of history and switching to the ontology of the dead body. In order to do this I look through these publications and indicate which threads could help work out the excellent, innovative, and fresh conception of Nekros. The main part of the article is a detailed discussion of this. In the other part, I consider how to interpret more traditionally a past description like “cultural memory” and whether Domańska’s works accidentally invalidate them. I suggest a short statement of Marcin Napiórkowski’s and Stephen Marks’ works to show closer (Marks) and further (Napiórkowski) parallels or completely different presentations of similar problems.

Go to article

Authors and Affiliations

Marta Tomczok
Download PDF Download RIS Download Bibtex

Abstract

In this article I present the problem of identity of objects (that persist in time and space) and their identification (also in time and space, when these objects persist and change their location) indicated in the title of the paper. I therefore present an outline of P.F. Strawson’s proposal, but also a purely formal approach that can be found in formal sciences (logic and mathematics). In the final part I give some ontological solution to Strawson’s research. It is a solution based on formal considerations within the so-called ontologically oriented versions of modal and temporal logics, which I proposed in my book Indywidua. Idee. Pojęcia (2008).

Go to article

Authors and Affiliations

Janusz Kaczmarek
ORCID: ORCID
Download PDF Download RIS Download Bibtex

Abstract

In this paper I take up one of the fundamental themes of ontology concerning the proper understanding of such ontological objects as ideal qualities, properties (features) and tropes. These objects, i.e. properties, qualities and tropes, help us understand more fully what an object in itself (substance, being, object) happens to be. The aim of this work is to present Ingarden’s position on this subject, but also to present a certain new formal solution that uses tools of topological ontology. The background for the problems here is to be found in the works of Aristotle, Ch. Wolff and N. Hartmann.
Go to article

Authors and Affiliations

Janusz Kaczmarek
1
ORCID: ORCID

  1. Uniwersytet Łódzki, Instytut Filozofii, ul. Lindleya 3/5, 90-131 Łódź
Download PDF Download RIS Download Bibtex

Abstract

In the first part of the article, I reconstruct the philosophical thoughts of Czesław Białobrzeski, a Polish philosophizing physicist. In the second part, I outline his biography and contribution to the development of physics. Philosophical reflections of Białobrzeski formed based on the leading issues in physics of the late 19th and mainly 20th century. He carried out his considerations in close connection to his scientific practice. The activity of the Polish scientist takes place in the formation and development period of quantum mechanics. Białobrzeski, similarly to many other physicists of the time, was well aware of the necessity of coherent explanation of the fundamentally new phenomena of the quantum mechanics. His take on the subject is rather original—he referred to the classical, philosophical theory of categories and proposed its ontological interpretation.
Go to article

Authors and Affiliations

Mariusz Mazurek
1

  1. Instytut Filozofii i Socjologii PAN, ul. Nowy Świat 72, 00–330 Warszawa
Download PDF Download RIS Download Bibtex

Abstract

The aim of the article is to reconstruct the cardinal theses and assumptions of the materialistic-dialectical ontology in the post-Stalinist Marxist scientific philosophy, often described as "Eastern Marxism". Basing on the source literature covering the works of the most eminent Polish (Stefan Amsterdamski, Stanisław Butryn, Helena Eilstein, Władysław Krajewski, Jan Such, Wiesław Sztumski and others) and Soviet (Fedosseyev, Konstantinov, Szeptulin, Rubinshtajn, etc.) philosophers which studied the links between dialectical materialism and natural sciences, I claim that postwar Marxist scientism clarifies the concise intuitions of the classics of Marxism regarding the nature and assumptions of dialectical materialism, especially the dialectic of nature. Contrary to the current interpretations of the sources of dogmatism in Marxism as the dominant ontological assumption of dialectical and natural materialism, according to these findings, it turns out that after its post-war modernization, the dialectical ontology was cleared of numerous dogmas and misunderstandings. Moreover, it turns out to be consistent with the general assumptions of the anti-Stalinist Marxist social and political philosophy.
Go to article

Authors and Affiliations

Damian Winczewski
1

  1. UMCS, Instytut Filozofii, Pl. M. Skłodowskiej-Curie 4, Lublin
Download PDF Download RIS Download Bibtex

Abstract

In this paper I present Bertrand Russell’s contacts with Polish readers and outstanding Polish writers. In paragraphs 2 and 3 I discuss books by Russell that were published in Poland and mention his personal contacts and correspondence. Russell exchanged letters with L. Chwistek, J. Conrad‑Korzeniowski, M. Dziewicki, G. Herling-‑Grudziński, S. Leśniewski, W. Lutosławski and A. Tarski. Interesting comments on his philosophy were offered by M. Ossowska, K. Twardowski, J. Salamucha and M. Heitzman. Paragraphs 4 and 5 discuss the influence that Russell’s logical ideas have exerted on the development of logic in Poland, especially in the works of L. Chwistek and S. Leśniewski.
Go to article

Authors and Affiliations

Jan Woleński
1
ORCID: ORCID

  1. Wyższa Szkoła Informatyki i Zarządzania w Rzeszowie, Katedra Nauk Spo-łecznych, ul. Sucharskiego 2, 35-225 Rzeszów
Download PDF Download RIS Download Bibtex

Abstract

An enormous output of Bertrand Russell breaks down into three groups. The first consists of works on logic, especially on philosophy of mathematics. But the program of reducing mathematics to logic, instead of providing certainty that Russell was looking for, multiplied our doubts. As a by‑product of these works, a program of logical analysis of ordinary language emerged and exerted a huge impact on the history of philosophy of the 20th century. But it did not fulfil the original hopes connected with it. The second group contains results of ontological and epistemological investigations. Here Russell achieved nothing, and what he proposed lay beyond the mainstream of 20th‑century ontology and epistemology. The third group was an outline of a social utopia, addressed to the general public. Professional philosophers ignored these works by Russell, and as a possible program to build a better world, they have become obsolete.
Go to article

Authors and Affiliations

Wojciech Sady
1
ORCID: ORCID

  1. Uniwersytet Śląski w Katowicach, Instytut Filozofii, ul. Bankowa 11, 40-007 Katowice
Download PDF Download RIS Download Bibtex

Abstract

The aim of this paper is to highlight the relationship between normative theory and social ontology through an analysis of John Rawls’s concept of ‘well‑ordered society’. By expressing the ontological assumptions underlying Rawls’s theory, it is possible to better understand the role of practices and institutions in A Theory of Justice and to counter some of the criticisms levelled against Rawls’s institutionalism. The proposed interpretation of Rawls’s theory may be recognized as a contribution to the interactionist approach in the field of social ontology.
Go to article

Bibliography

Berkey B. (2016), Against Rawlsian Institutionalism about Justice, „Social Theory and Practice” 42 (4), s. 706–732.
Ciszewski W. (2020), Rozum i demokracja. Wprowadzenie do koncepcji rozumu publicznego Johna Rawlsa, Kraków: Wydawnictwo Uniwersytetu Jagiellońskiego.
Cohen G.A. (1997), Where the Action Is: On the Site of Distributive Justice, „Philosophy & Public Affairs” 26 (1), s. 3–30.
Diver N. (2004), Institutions and Social Justice [nieopublikowana rozprawa doktorska], University of Pennsylvania.
Frega R. (2018), The Social Ontology of Democracy, „Journal of Social Ontology” 4 (2), s. 157–185.
Kwarciński T. (2006), Możliwości czy dobra pierwotne? Dyskusja Amartyi Sena z Johnem Rawlsem na temat właściwej przestrzeni sprawiedliwości, „Roczniki Filozoficzne” 54 (1), s. 81–106.
Mandle J. (2009), Rawls’s „A Theory of Justice”: An Introduction, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Mandle J., Reidy D.A. (red.) (2014), The Cambridge Rawls Lexicon, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Murphy L.B. (1998), Institutions and the Demands of Justice, „Philosophy & Public Affairs” 27 (4), s. 251–291.
Nozick R. (1974), Anarchy, State and Utopia, New York: Basic Books.
Pettit P. (2005), Rawls’s Political Ontology, „Politics, Philosophy & Economics” 4 (2), s. 157–174.
Pettit P. (2006), Rawls’s Peoples, w: R. Martin, D.A. Reidy (red.), Rawls’s Law of Peoples: A Realistic Utopia, Hoboken, NJ: Wiley‑Blackwell, s. 38–55.
Rawls A. (2009), An Essay on Two Conceptions of Social Order, „Journal of Classical Sociology” 9 (4), s. 500–520.
Rawls J. (1955), Two Concepts of Rules, „The Philosophical Review” 64 (1), s. 3–32.
Rawls J. (2009), Teoria sprawiedliwości, przeł. M. Panufnik, J. Pasek, A. Romaniuk, S. Szymański, Warszawa: Wydawnictwo Naukowe PWN.
Sen A. (2009), The Idea of Justice, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Go to article

Authors and Affiliations

Wojciech Graboń
1
ORCID: ORCID
Marcin Woźny
2 3
ORCID: ORCID

  1. Uniwersytet Warszawski, Szkoła Doktorska Nauk Humanistycznych, ul. Krakowskie Przedmieście 26/28, 00‑927 Warszawa
  2. Uniwersytet Warszawski, Wydział Filozofii, ul. Krakowskie Przedmieście 3, 00‑927 Warszawa
  3. Uniwersytet Warszawski, Wydział Prawa i Administracji, ul. Krakowskie Przedmieście 26/28, 00‑927 Warszawa
Download PDF Download RIS Download Bibtex

Abstract

In this paper Roman Ingarden’s theory of meaning is presented. It turns out to be an interesting mixture of mentalist and anti-mentalist intuitions. Mentalists, like e.g. Edmund Husserl, claim that linguistic meaning has its source in the fact that our words express our mental states, while anti‑mentalists try to situate meanings outside our minds.
Go to article

Authors and Affiliations

Arkadiusz Chrudzimski
1
ORCID: ORCID

  1. Uniwersytet Jagielloński, Instytut Filozofii, ul. Grodzka 52, 31-044 Kraków
Download PDF Download RIS Download Bibtex

Abstract

Formalization of a set of beliefs expressed in one language consists in translating them into sentences of another language. The characteristic property of a good formalization is that the target language is correctly chosen and the translations precisely reflect the meaning of the original sentences. In the paper a formalization of ontology of situations (given by Professor Bogusław Wolniewicz) is discussed. I argue that this is an example of a perfect solution of the problem.

Go to article

Authors and Affiliations

Anna Wójtowicz
Download PDF Download RIS Download Bibtex

Abstract

Żyjemy w czasach, w których wzrasta znaczenie sztucznej inteligencji oraz oczekiwanie na coraz bardziej inteligentne systemy. W miarę jak sztuczna inteligencja i inteligentne roboty przejmują od człowieka różne funkcje, pojawiają się pytania o rodzaj i zakres ich działania w stosunku do możliwości człowieka. Proces ten rodzi pytanie, czy można wskazać takie sfery ludzkiej aktywności, które nie mogą być powielone przez inteligentne programy lub roboty? Na pierwszy rzut oka takimi własnościami człowieka jest emocjonalność, uczuciowość i twórczość. W niniejszym artykule analizuję, czy inteligentne roboty mogłyby być twórcze artystycznie i zastępować w tym procesie człowieka. Zakładam, że choć trudno jest w dzisiejszych czasach wskazaćnowatorsko twórcze roboty, to równie trudno podawać w wątpliwość fakt, że roboty w jakimś sensie tworzą sztukę. Wprawdzie z dzisiejszej perspektywy natura ludzka jest jeszcze pod tym względem niepowielalna przez roboty i sztuczną inteligencję, ale równocześnie wykracza się w niej coraz bardziej poza postawę antropocentryczną, przyjmując, że twórczość nie jest wyłącznąwłasnością, lecz jedynie właściwością człowieka, i że mówiąc o sztucznej inteligencji, można dopuścić myśl o uprawianej przez nią twórczości.

Go to article

Authors and Affiliations

Sidey Myoo
Download PDF Download RIS Download Bibtex

Abstract

The paper attempts to place John Rawls’s social theory in an ontological frame of ideas. Józef M. Bocheński’s theory of systems was chosen to describe social reality without prejudging its role in the adequate theory. By adopting this approach the author presents several issues one by one: the characteristics of political philosophy and its relation to the ontology of social reality, Bocheński’s systems theory, the analysis of the industrial enterprise as a model example of a heterogeneous, dynamic and organic system, and Rawls’s structure of society. All this is done in terms of systems theory. The resulting outcome provides, among other things, a formal definition of Rawls’s basic social structure expressed in the language of systems theory, and it supports the thesis that the synthetic entity responsible for social functioning, such as the state, is correlated with the principles of justice as proposed by Rawls.
Go to article

Bibliography

Bertalanffy L. (1984), Ogólna teoria systemów. Podstawy, rozwój, zastosowania, przeł. E. Woydyłło‑Woźniak, Warszawa: Państwowe Wydawnictwo Naukowe.
Bocheński J.M. (1986), The Concept of the Free Society, „The Monist” 69 (2), s. 207– 215.
Bocheński J.M. (1993), Przyczynek do filozofii przedsiębiorstwa przemysłowego, przeł. J. Garewicz, w: J.M. Bocheński, Logika i filozofia, red. J. Parys, Biblioteka Współczesnych Filozofów, Warszawa: Wydawnictwo Naukowe PWN.
Bunge M. (1979), Treatise on Basic Philosophy, vol. 4: Ontology II: A World of Systems, Dordrecht – Boston – London: D. Reidel Publishing Company.
Ingarden R. (1972), Książeczka o człowieku, Kraków: Wydawnictwo Literackie.
Ingarden R. (1974), Wstęp do fenomenologii Husserla, przeł. A. Półtawski, Warszawa: Państwowe Wydawnictwo Naukowe.
Ingarden R. (1987), Spór o istnienie świata, t. I, t. II, cz. 1 i 2, wyd. III, Warszawa: Państwowe Wydawnictwo Naukowe.
Kaczmarek J. (2008), Indywidua. Idee. Pojęcia. Badania z zakresu ontologii sformalizowanej, Łódź: Wydawnictwo Uniwersytetu Łódzkiego.
Kaczmarek J. (2016), Atom ontologiczny: atom substancji, „Przegląd Filozoficzny – Nowa Seria” 4 (100), s. 109–124.
Rawls J. (1971), A Theory of Justice, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Rawls J. (1993), Political Liberalism, New York: Columbia University Press.
Rawls J. (1999), The Law of Peoples, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Rawls J. (2001), Justice as Fairness: A Restatement, red. E. Kelly, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Stróżewski W. (2003), Ontologia, Kraków: Znak – Aureus.
Wenar L. (2021), John Rawls, w: E.N. Zalta (red.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Summer 2021 Edition, https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2021/entries/rawls/.
Go to article

Authors and Affiliations

Janusz Kaczmarek
1
ORCID: ORCID

  1. Uniwersytet Łódzki, Instytut Filozofii, ul. Lindleya 3/5, 90-131 Łódź
Download PDF Download RIS Download Bibtex

Abstract

The paper tries to defend the thesis that it is impossible to decide upon moral issues without any references to the ontology of the world we live in. An illustrative example of the main argumentation line is the choice made by Cypher—a second plan character in the movie Matrix. Cypher decides to betray human rebels fighting against machines for freedom and, as a reward, accepts affluent life in the virtual reality. His choice seems to be superficially reprehensible because of the abandonment of the real world and authentic life. However, one can argue that the dichotomy between the real and virtual world is seeming. By choosing the virtual reality Cypher decided to act in a world which, like the real world, makes it possible to be a moral subject and enables authentic experience. The difference between both the worlds lies in the type of determination limiting any conscious subject. Cypher prefers to live in a world determined by the algorithm of Matrix more than in a world where his behaviour is determined by genes and other biological factors.

Go to article

Authors and Affiliations

Jacek Gurczyński
Download PDF Download RIS Download Bibtex

Abstract

Elzenbergowska teza o obiektywnej tożsamości dobra i piękna nie jest przekonywająca. Problem można zanalizować na gruncie Wittgensteinowskiej ontologii sytuacji, co daje lepsze widoki na jego rozwiązanie. Zbiory stanów rzeczy dobrych (D) i pięknych (P) ani się nie pokrywają, ani nie przecinają, ani D nie zawiera się w P. Nie da się wskazać dla D i P cechy rodzajowej i różnicy gatunkowej. P i D dają się jedynie definiować cząstkowo – przez przykłady i zbliżanie się do ich zbiorów wyczerpujących. W języku naturalnym wyróżnia się wiele odmian dobra i piękna, rozmaicie powiązanych, na przykład „piękno moralne”, „moralną brzydotę”, ale też „brzydotę amoralną”, a nawet „szpetne dobro”. Jednakże zbiory P i D (oraz B i Z – stanów rzeczy szpetnych i złych) są rozłączne. Otóż w konkretnej sytuacji pięknej może tkwić abstrakcyjny stan rzeczy odnoszący się do dobra, a w konkretnej sytuacji dobrej – abstrakcyjny stan rzeczy odnoszący się do piękna. Te abstrakcyjne „rdzenie” sytuacji mogą piękno intersubiektywnie „zabarwiać” dobrem, a dobro pięknem.
Go to article

Authors and Affiliations

Paweł Okołowski
Download PDF Download RIS Download Bibtex

Abstract

This paper sets out to characterise and analyse logical atomism of Bertrand Russell. Main tenets of that theory are described by reference to Russell’s lecture Facts and Propositions (1918) and to other publications by that author. The essential claims of Russell’s position are discussed and confronted with tenets of ontology of situations developed by Bogusław Wolniewicz, a position inspired by logical atomism of Ludwig Wittgenstein. The author argues that several of Russell’s theses on logical atomism can be interpreted in the light of Wolniewicz’s ontology of situations. Finally, some minor concluding remarks are offered that can help to develop an ontology conceived in the spirit of the ontology of logical atomism. 366 Janusz Kaczmarek
Go to article

Authors and Affiliations

Janusz Kaczmarek
1
ORCID: ORCID

  1. Uniwersytet Łódzki, Instytut Filozofii, ul. Lindleya 3/5, 90-131 Łódź
Download PDF Download RIS Download Bibtex

Abstract

The article focuses on the problem of possible relations of a work of art to the Absolute Being. The essence of the discussed issue can be put as a question: Is it possible, without mentioning God explicitly, to declare that a piece of art, as a carrier of beauty, indicates His presence? Relating to a number of Roman Ingarden’s significant statements that refer to metaphysical experience and the status of metaphysical qualities, and drawing upon Ingarden’s existential and ontological claims, the article presents metaphysical quality as a manifestation of existential dependence. This interpretation invokes the context of the primary being, and by extension, of the Absolute Being. If a work of art (or to be more precise, its concretization) is a carrier of aesthetic beauty through which a qualitative and metaphysical atmosphere emerges (and discloses its metaphysical quality) and if (as it is postulated in the interpretation suggested) it refers to the Absolute, then the thesis that beauty leads to God has been vindicated.
Go to article

Authors and Affiliations

Waldemar Kmiecikowski
1
ORCID: ORCID

  1. Uniwersytet im. Adama Mickiewicza w Poznaniu, Wydział Teologiczny, ul. Wieżowa 2/4, 61-111 Poznań
Download PDF Download RIS Download Bibtex

Abstract

Selected scientific contacts of Jacek Hawranek and Jan Zygmunt with Professor Bogusław Wolniewicz in the period from the end of the 1980s to the beginning of the 21st century are presented in this essay. They concerned the algebraic aspects of the ontology of situations and from one moment – one only question that was posed by Wolniewicz in his note A question about join-semilattices (Bulletin of the Section of Logic, 19/3, 1990, pp. 108–108), and resulted in the Hawranek & Zygmunt paper Wokół pewnego zagadnienia z dziedziny półkrat górnych z jednością (“Some comments on a question about semilattices with unit”) (Acta Universitatis Wratislaviensis 1445, Logika 15 (1993), pp. 59–68) containing an answer to Wolniewicz’s question. The Hawranek & Zygmunt paper is reprinted below, and the essay might be also treated as a kind of an analytical and historical introduction to it. The story of contacts Wolniewicz – Hawranek & Zygmunt has been told with the help of the preserved correspondence between the three persons. In his letters Professor Wolniewicz appears as a passionate researcher, open to discussion, ready to share his research successes and difficulties with others.

Go to article

Authors and Affiliations

Jan Zygmunt
Download PDF Download RIS Download Bibtex

Abstract

In his 1903 monograph Principles of Mathematics Bertrand Russell formulated a theory which interpreted a proposition expressed by a sentence as a unitary bond of referents (meanings) of its parts. In the paper I argue that the problem he faced in his attempt to define the unity of proposition is a special case of a wider philosophical problem of the relation between language and the world. Mentioned for the first time by Plato in Parmenides and then repeated by Aristotle in Metaphysics, infinite regress formulated as ʻthe third man argument’ presented a problem for Francis Bradley, Bertrand Russell and Gottlob Frege. It was reformulated in syntactic terms by Hans Reichenbach and used by Donald Davidson as an argument against referential semantics. The conclusion of the paper is as follows: ʻthe third man argument’ is a result of projecting syntactic structures of language on metaphysically conceived referential semantics. It does not undermine ontology conceived as an investigation of possible beings.
Go to article

Authors and Affiliations

Janusz Maciaszek
1
ORCID: ORCID

  1. Uniwersytet Łódzki, Instytut Filozofii, ul. Lindleya 3/5, 90-131 Łódź
Download PDF Download RIS Download Bibtex

Abstract

This article is an attempt to present a comprehensive view of the poetry of Józef Czechowicz in the context of Martin Heidegger's fundamental ontology. Czechowicz's poetic work, the article argues, is an exploration of mutual relations of the basic ontological categories of being and nothingness ( das Sein and das Nichts). They constitute the philosophical foundations of the purely literary tensions that can be detected in all comprehensive accounts of his work, such as the opposition of Arcadia and Catastrophy (Tadeusz Kłak) or the discussion of the ‘bright’ and the ‘dark’ strain in the poetry of the Second Avant-garde (Jerzy Kwiatkowski).
Go to article

Authors and Affiliations

Marcin Całbecki
1
ORCID: ORCID

  1. Uniwersytet Gdański
Download PDF Download RIS Download Bibtex

Abstract

In 2020, in Poland, a national commemoration of two eminent religious philosophers was celebrated: it was dedicated to the memory of Friar J.M. Bocheński O.P. and Pope St. John Paul II. In the paper, I recapitulate fundamental ideas of The Logic of Religion (1965) by the former author and sum up the key issues of the doctoral thesis The Doctrine of Faith in St. John of the Cross (1948) by the latter. I also mention St. John Henry Cardinal Newman’s Grammar of Ascent (1870), because in Polish translation this book is entitled A Logic of Faith. In order to compare those heterogeneous conceptions of religious faith I reach out to logical semiotics, and using its tools I try to find a symbolic meaning of religious speech that could be accepted equally by religious thinkers and by non‑believers. I propose to understand religious speech as having not only literal sense, and not only a metaphysical meaning, but also, as I claim, the power to activate values that guide human behavior. I hope this is a conciliatory proposition because it places semiotics on a neutral footing among religious dogmas. In this perspective, mysticism can be described as a pragmatic aspect of language that emerges when a user refers to a transcendent reality.
Go to article

Bibliography

1. Alighieri D. (2004), Biesiada, przeł. M. Bartkowiak‑Lerch, Kęty: Antyk.
2. Bocheński J.M. (1988), Między logiką a wiarą. Z Józefem M. Bocheńskim rozmawia Jan Parys, Montricher: Les Editions Noir Sur Blanc.
3. Bocheński J.M. (1990), Logika religii, przeł. S. Magala, Warszawa: Instytut Wydawniczy Pax.
4. Bocheński J.M. (1993), Sens życia, Kraków: Philed.
5. Bocheński J.M. (1994), Sto zabobonów, Kraków: Philed.
6. Gronczewska A. (2009), Szyfrant, który sprawił cud, „Dziennik Łódzki”, https:// dzienniklodzki.pl/szyfrant-ktory-sprawil-cud/ar/185093
7. Jan od Krzyża św. (1975), Dzieła, t. I–II, przeł. o. Bernard od Matki Bożej, wyd. III, Kraków: Wydawnictwo oo. Karmelitów Bosych.
8. Newman J.H. (1989), Logika wiary, przeł. P. Boharczyk, Warszawa: Instytut Wydawniczy Pax.
9. Poe E.A. (1986), Złoty żuk, w: tenże, Opowiadania, t. 1, przeł. S. Wyrzykowski, Warszawa: Czytelnik.
10. Pseudo‑Dionizy Areopagita (1997), Teologia symboliczna, w: tenże, Pisma teologiczne, przeł. M. Dzielska, Kraków: Znak.
11. Wojtyła K. (1959), Ocena możliwości zbudowania etyki chrześcijańskiej przy założeniach systemu Maksa Schelera, Lublin: Towarzystwo Naukowe KUL.
12. Wojtyła K. (1990), Zagadnienie wiary w dziełach św. Jana od Krzyża, przeł. o. Leonard od Męki Pańskiej OCD, Kraków: Wydawnictwo oo. Karmelitów Bosych.
13. Zieliński T. (1999), Chrześcijaństwo antyczne, Religie Świata Antycznego, T. VI, Toruń: Wydawnictwo Adam Marszałek.


Go to article

Authors and Affiliations

Łukasz Kowalik
1
ORCID: ORCID

  1. Uniwersytet Warszawski, Wydział Filozofii, Redakcja „Przeglądu Filozoficznego”, ul. Krakowskie Przedmieście 3, 00-927 Warszawa
Download PDF Download RIS Download Bibtex

Abstract

This contribution to the critical discussion of Ryszard Nycz’s Culture as Verb draws on his use of the parts-of-speech model to submit another formula of conceptualizing culture, based on the adverb, and complementary to the already existing approaches. They can be divided into three classes: those that treat culture as adjective (i.e. all epiphenomenal interpretations which view culture as a set of attributes), those that treat it as noun (i.e. an object, a separate academic discipline), and those that focus on action and the processual nature of culture (hence culture as verb), and even – in association with pragmatist and performative theories of language and the more recent ‘Activist Turn’ in the social sciences – have come to regard culture as culture-in-the-making, constituted and sustained by action (activities, performances). Most important for the adverbial approach are the modalities of culture, manifested in a variety of life styles. The study of culture as adverb (‘how’) can be pursued independently of the trench wars of cultural determinists and functionalists. Responding directly to Culture as Verb, qualifi ed as, chiefl y, an epistemological study, the article calls for a closer examination of the ontological implications of Nycz’s project of reinventing the humanities.

Go to article

Authors and Affiliations

Dorota Wolska

This page uses 'cookies'. Learn more